decoration decoration
Stories

GROKLAW
When you want to know more...
decoration
For layout only
Home
Archives
Site Map
Search
About Groklaw
Awards
Legal Research
Timelines
ApplevSamsung
ApplevSamsung p.2
ArchiveExplorer
Autozone
Bilski
Cases
Cast: Lawyers
Comes v. MS
Contracts/Documents
Courts
DRM
Gordon v MS
GPL
Grokdoc
HTML How To
IPI v RH
IV v. Google
Legal Docs
Lodsys
MS Litigations
MSvB&N
News Picks
Novell v. MS
Novell-MS Deal
ODF/OOXML
OOXML Appeals
OraclevGoogle
Patents
ProjectMonterey
Psystar
Quote Database
Red Hat v SCO
Salus Book
SCEA v Hotz
SCO Appeals
SCO Bankruptcy
SCO Financials
SCO Overview
SCO v IBM
SCO v Novell
SCO:Soup2Nuts
SCOsource
Sean Daly
Software Patents
Switch to Linux
Transcripts
Unix Books

Gear

Groklaw Gear

Click here to send an email to the editor of this weblog.


You won't find me on Facebook


Donate

Donate Paypal


No Legal Advice

The information on Groklaw is not intended to constitute legal advice. While Mark is a lawyer and he has asked other lawyers and law students to contribute articles, all of these articles are offered to help educate, not to provide specific legal advice. They are not your lawyers.

Here's Groklaw's comments policy.


What's New

STORIES
No new stories

COMMENTS last 48 hrs
No new comments


Sponsors

Hosting:
hosted by ibiblio

On servers donated to ibiblio by AMD.

Webmaster
Fair Use: Affirmative Defense or Right? Do I Have to Choose?
Sunday, September 09 2007 @ 01:40 PM EDT

After all I went through trying to figure out if I was allowed to link to some Pavarotti videos the other day, I decided I'd better study a bit more about fair use. I've also since gotten a fair amount of email about the Copyright Alliance's claim that fair use is not a consumer right, but merely an affirmative defense. That was inspirational, I must say, and it got me to actually do the work of digging to find out if that statement is true or not.

The first thing that I thought of was, naturally, the affirmative defenses in the SCO v Novell litigation. Do you remember, when Novell accused SCO of slander of title, SCO pled the First Amendment as an affirmative defense? Yet, the fact that the First Amendment's free speech rights can be used as an affirmative defense surely doesn't mean it's therefore no longer a right. So I started with the conclusion that it is possible for an affirmative defense to also be a right. Free speech is a Constitutionally protected right. So, what about fair use? I didn't know, so I decided to try to find out.

Here's what I've found so far. I'm just a paralegal, and this is just my research, so if you really need to know the answer to this question, you need to ask your lawyer. I've merely collected some resources for you that I thought were useful for the discussion, and it isn't all that there is to find, I'm sure, but my thought was that it would help us to reasonably follow the discussion that the Copyright Alliance has started. And it also raises a question in my mind I don't know the answer to, so I thought I would throw it out there so others who know more than I do can think about it.

As you will see, this is a discussion that's actually been going on since at least 2002, and I gather from my research that some would like it if fair use *wasn't* a right, because then DRM can block it 100% without having to worry about us little people. But there is a case just decided by the Court of Appeals in the 10th Circuit that I think you'll find interesting and on point, Golan v. Gonzales [PDF], that indicates to me, if I've understood it correctly, that blocking all fair use would implicate the First Amendment. Yes, that is the same court that SCO will likely be appealing to one day, although not right now, thanks to Judge Kimball's ruling on Friday. I will present it as text also, for your convenience, but again, as always go by the PDF for anything that matters. I strive for accuracy, but being merely human, I can't ensure it.

From my reading, I think it indicates that fair use has First Amendment implications, which would elevate it much higher than a mere "consumer right" such as a state might legislate to give you. The order explains copyright law and how it works in some detail, and that's useful all by itself, and it talks specifically about fair use. I've marked the parts I think are most important in colored text.

The case made headlines for a different reason, but aside from being interesting in its own right, we can glean from it quite a lot about what fair use is by seeing what the court wrote about it. The ruling calls it "a guarantee" of breathing space. I have to qualify that by the fact that fair use can be wiped out by a successful argument in a particular case that a practice, if widespread, could destroy the work's value. Here's what Larry Lessig, who represented the plaintiffs, explained about the ruling:

The 10th Circuit decided our appeal in Golan v. Gonzales today. In a unanimous vote, the Court held that the "traditional contours of copyright protection" described in Eldred as the trigger for First Amendment review extend beyond the two "traditional First Amendment safeguards" mentioned by the Court in that case. It thus remanded the case to the District Court to evaluate section 514 of the Uruguay Round Agreements Act (“URAA”) under the First Amendment, which removed material from the public domain.

This is a very big victory. The government had argued in this case, and in related cases, that the only First Amendment review of a copyright act possible was if Congress changed either fair use or erased the idea/expression dichotomy. We, by contrast, have argued consistently that in addition to those two, Eldred requires First Amendment review when Congress changes the "traditional contours of copyright protection." In Golan, the issue is a statute that removes work from the public domain. In a related case now on cert to the Supreme Court, Kahle v. Gonzales, the issue is Congress's change from an opt-in system of copyright to an opt-out system of copyright. That too, we have argued, is a change in a "traditional contour of copyright protection." Under the 10th Circuit's rule, it should merit 1st Amendment review as well. ...The opinion by Judge Henry is well worth the read. The argument was one [of] the best I have seen.

Did you notice the description of fair use as being one of the two First Amendment issues in copyright law analysis that both parties agreed exist? Unless the Copyright Alliance wishes to argue that the First Amendment is not a right any more, I'd think that settles that part of the discussion right there. I think it's implied then that removing fair use from copyright law would involve First Amendment scrutiny, to say the least, and from this ruling, I don't think Congress would have the right to legislate a death of fair use, since it'd be a change to the traditional copyright system of such magnitude it would at least have to pass First Amendment scrutiny. And how could it? I can't follow that logically. Maybe they'll find a way, but it's a very high bar. The Constitution stands in the way of the Congress here.

So the subtle next question in my mind is about DRM: if someday computers required DRM to even boot up, and all computers must have this, and you can't under any circumstances legally get around it to access documents, ebooks, music, and graphics, what has happened to fair use? On what basis would it be legal, by that I mean Constitutional, to deliberately or even accidentally prevent it? After all, if you can't physically make use of it -- poof, it's gone. Fair use becomes a nullity. And you're talking about a First Amendment right here, from what I'm reading. Even now, if even one copyright holder completely blocks all fair use by DRMing the work, what has he done to fair use? So when the Copyright Alliance talks of fair use as being merely an affirmative defense, what is it saying? And is that so?

I am not saying it couldn't happen, but it would be huge and it would have to pass First Amendment scrutiny, if that could even happen. It hasn't, from what I've seen in my digging, happened yet.

Here's the description of the Golan case on the Center for Internet and Society's website, which filed the litigation for Golan and the other plaintiffs, under the title, "Victory In The 10th Circuit: What Enters The Public Domain Stays In The Public Domain":

The Tenth Circuit handed us a momentous victory today, holding that the Uruguay Round Agreements Act ("URAA") altered the "traditional contours of copyright protection" by resurrecting copyright protection for works that had fallen into the public domain, thus contravening the "bedrock principle of copyright law that works in the public domain remain in the public domain."

While this decision does not invalidate the URAA, it does hold that the URAA must pass either strict or intermediate First Amendment scrutiny on remand.

There is an earlier case about pleading fair use as an affirmative defense, Harper & Row v. Nation Enterprises, and here's a lawyer, William Patry, who was involved in the case, discussing it. But if you read the ruling, it wasn't about whether fair use is or is not a right. The case involved whether a prepublication leak was fair use or not. The analysis of published works and unpublished isn't identical. As the ruling puts it, "the scope of fair use is narrower with respect to unpublished works." Not everyone was thrilled with that decision, by the way, including some of the justices on the Supreme Court, who wrote a dissent. But let's look at how it defines and explains fair use:

(c) In view of the First Amendment's protections embodied in the Act's distinction between copyrightable expression and uncopyrightable facts and ideas, and the latitude for scholarship and comment traditionally afforded by fair use, there is no warrant for expanding, as respondents contend should be done, the fair use doctrine to what amounts to a public figure exception to copyright. Whether verbatim copying from a public figure's manuscript in a given case is or is not fair must be judged according to the traditional equities of fair use. Pp. 555-560.

Fair use is a mixed question of law and fact. Pacific & Southern Co. v. Duncan, 744 F.2d 1490, 1495, n. 8 (CA11 1984). Where the district court has found facts sufficient to evaluate each of the statutory factors, an appellate court "need not remand for further factfinding . . . [but] may conclude as a matter of law that [the challenged use] do[es] not qualify as a fair use of the copyrighted work." Id., at 1495. Thus whether The Nation article constitutes fair use under 107 must be reviewed in light of the principles discussed above. The factors enumerated in the section are not meant to be exclusive: "[S]ince the doctrine is an equitable rule of reason, no generally applicable definition is possible, and each case raising the question must be decided on its own facts." House Report, at 65. The four factors identified by Congress as especially relevant in determining whether the use was fair are: (1) the purpose and character of the use; (2) the nature of the copyrighted work; (3) the substantiality of the portion used in relation to the copyrighted work as a whole; (4) the effect on the potential market for or value of the copyrighted work.

Perhaps the Copyright Alliance would argue that the difficulty in coming up with a definition of fair use that would be generally applicable to all situations would argue against changing the warnings on movies. But this ruling defined it pretty clearly. At least you could let people know that they have a fair use right they might want to study up on and you could mention the nonexclusive four factors to give a hint. Here's my favorite sentence in the ruling:

We agree with the Court of Appeals that copyright is intended to increase and not to impede the harvest of knowledge.

So, the idea is that after the term of exclusive right to the copyright holder expires, the work goes into the public domain and at that point, the public reaps the harvest. The Golan case was about how long is too long and about pulling works back out of the public domain and putting a copyright back on a work, but if we think about DRM a minute, how can a world where everything is DRM'd forever pass First Amendment scrutiny, I wonder, since it wipes away fair use completely? If all works are DRM'd and they can never get free of it, would that increase or impede the harvest of knowledge, which is the stated purpose of the law? There are no time limits that I know of on DRM'd works, after all, even if it didn't block you from access in the first place totally. Well. I'm talking about legal access. Here's another sentence that bears on this discussion, I think:

The copyright owner's rights, however, are subject to certain statutory exceptions. 107-118. Among these is 107 which codifies the traditional privilege of other authors to make "fair use" of an earlier writer's work.

Here fair use is called a privilege. But notice what the ruling goes on to say about what it calls a duty of the copyright holder to agree to certain fair uses:

Fair use was traditionally defined as "a privilege in others than the owner of the copyright to use the copyrighted material in a reasonable manner without his consent." ... The statutory formulation of the defense of fair use in the Copyright Act reflects the intent of Congress to codify the common-law doctrine.... Section 107 requires a case-by-case determination whether a particular use is fair, and the statute notes four nonexclusive factors to be considered. This approach was "intended to restate the [pre-existing] judicial doctrine of fair use, not to change, narrow, or enlarge it in any way."... "[T]he author's consent to a reasonable use of his copyrighted works ha[d] always been implied by the courts as a necessary incident of the constitutional policy of promoting the progress of science and the useful arts, since a prohibition of such use would inhibit subsequent writers from attempting to improve upon prior works and thus . . . frustrate the very ends sought to be attained." Ball 260. Professor Latman, in a study of the doctrine of fair use commissioned by Congress for the revision effort, see Sony Corp. of America v. Universal City Studios, Inc., 464 U.S.... summarized prior law as turning on the "importance of the material copied or performed from the point of view of the reasonable copyright owner. In other words, would the reasonable copyright owner have consented to the use?"

Let's read one part again: "...a prohibition of such use would inhibit subsequent writers from attempting to improve upon prior works and thus . . . frustrate the very ends sought to be attained." So, here are my questions: if the copyright owner has an implied duty to consent to reasonable fair use, in order for the purpose of copyright law be fulfilled, does DRM -- or could DRM -- run afoul of the First Amendment if it makes all fair use impossible? Does it matter that copyright holders have this implied obligation? How much does it matter? If the copyright holder prevents fair use 100% forever by means of DRM, how will that copyright holder fulfill his or her implied duty to reasonably assent to fair use? What, if anything, can outweigh that duty?

You'll see if you read that Harper ruling all the way through that the court made a distinction for unpublished works:

In sum, the traditional doctrine of fair use, as embodied in the Copyright Act, does not sanction the use made by The Nation of these copyrighted materials. Any copyright infringer may claim to benefit the public by increasing public access to the copyrighted work. See Pacific & Southern Co. v. Duncan, 744 F.2d, at 1499-1500. But Congress has not designed, and we see no warrant for judicially imposing, a "compulsory license" permitting unfettered access to the unpublished copyrighted expression of public figures.

The magazine had scooped a book by former President Gerald Ford, and published before the book or a Time magazine article about it could be published, giving away all the best parts, mostly word for word. So, the case was about that.

You can hear the oral arguments before the Supreme Court as MP3, also, if you find this interesting, or here.

It was a 6-3 decision, and Justice Brennan's dissent begins like this:

JUSTICE BRENNAN, with whom JUSTICE WHITE and JUSTICE MARSHALL join, dissenting. The Court holds that The Nation's quotation of 300 words from the unpublished 200,000-word manuscript of President Gerald R. Ford infringed the copyright in that manuscript, even though the quotations related to a historical event of undoubted significance - the resignation and pardon of President Richard M. Nixon. Although the Court pursues the laudable goal of protecting "the economic incentive to create and disseminate ideas," ante, at 558, this zealous defense of the copyright owner's prerogative will, I fear, stifle the broad dissemination of ideas and information copyright is intended to nurture. Protection of the copyright owner's economic interest is achieved in this case through an exceedingly narrow definition of the scope of fair use. The progress of arts and sciences and the robust public debate essential to an enlightened citizenry are ill served by this constricted reading of the fair use doctrine. See 17 U.S.C. 107. I therefore respectfully dissent.

He goes on to quote from the Sony case, where the court pointed out that authors have no natural right to their works:

"The enactment of copyright legislation by Congress under the terms of the Constitution is not based upon any natural right that the author has in his writings . . . but upon the ground that the welfare of the public will be served and progress of science and useful arts will be promoted by securing to authors for limited periods the exclusive rights to their writings." H. R. Rep. No. 2222, 60th Cong., 2d Sess., 7 (1909). Congress thus seeks to define the rights included in copyright so as to serve the public welfare and not necessarily so as to maximize an author's control over his or her product. The challenge of copyright is to strike the "difficult balance between the interests of authors and inventors in the control and exploitation of their writings and discoveries on the one hand, and society's competing interest in the free flow of ideas, information, and commerce on the other hand." Sony Corp. of America v. Universal City Studios, Inc., 464 U.S. 417, 429 (1984).

So if we wish to talk about who has rights and who doesn't, I think we need to acknowledge that copyright holders have no natural rights to exclusion, only what the law grants, and it grants it for a purpose, which purpose isn't 100% control to the copyright holder. I found this recent thread where you'll see that lawyers are not united on this question with regard to what fair use is, a right or affirmative defense, but they are thinking about it, and they figure someday the Supreme Court will make it clearer.

The entertainment industry may want fair use not to be a right so they don't have to provide it and can DRM it into nothingness, mainly I would guess because no one can figure out yet how to DRM something *and* provide fair use. It's a real issue, and I don't mock the seriousness of the problem. If everyone agreed to just abide by the law and quit bypassing copyright law, it'd be fine and dandy. If we all understood it, that would be a start. Or if the consequences of digital copying were not so potentially huge, maybe everyone could relax some. According to The new "copyspeak" by Computer Electronics Association CEO Gary Shapiro, the argument that fair use is not a right, merely an affirmative defense has been going on since at least 2002:

Fair use rights--the right of consumers to make copies of copyrighted materials for their personal use--are guaranteed to consumers by statute, and applied judicially on a case-by-case basis. This means that, while some consumer practices ultimately could be adjudicated as either fair use or infringement, there is scant basis for challenging them as criminal activity, as copyspeak would now have it.

In copyspeak, there is no such thing as fair use "rights," rather fair use is only an affirmative defense to copyright infringement and therefore not a right. But various recognized "rights" may only be asserted as affirmative defenses in a lawsuit. For example, in a slander suit, one may assert the First Amendment right but only as an affirmative defense; this does not diminish the fact that the right exists. Time after time, practices of individuals that were initially equated with "piracy" or "theft" have been shown to be neutral, even beneficial, to copyright owners, and have been accepted as fair use. Think of the VCR and the Supreme Court decision holding that its use to tape full movies is completely legal.

It is, but I don't think Hollywood likes that even nonw. Anyway, I wanted to share all this with you, because if folks are trying to diminish, redraft, or get rid of a First Amendment right, I thought you'd want to know.

****************************************

UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS

TENTH CIRCUIT

___________________________________

LAWRENCE GOLAN; ESTATE OF
RICHARD KAPP; S.A. PUBLISHING
CO, IN C., d/b/a ESS.A.Y.
RECORDINGS; SYMPHONY OF THE
CANYONS; RON HALL d/b/a
FESTIVAL FILMS; and JOHN
McDONOUGH, d/b/a TIM ELESS
VIDEO ALTERNATIVES
INTERNATIONAL,

Plaintiffs-Appellants,

v.

ALBERTO R. GONZALES, in his
official capacity as Attorney General of
the United States; and MARYBETH
PETERS, Register of Copyrights,
Copyright Office of the
United States,

Defendants-Appellees,

INTERNATIONAL COALITION FOR
COPYRIGHT PROTECTION,

Amicus Curiae.

_______________________________________

No. 05-1259

______________________________________

Appeal from the United States District Court
for the District of Colorado
(D.C. No. 1:01-cv-01854 LTB-BNB)

Lawrence Lessig, Center for Internet and Society, Stanford Law School, Stanford California (Hugh Q. Gottschalk and Carolyn J. Fairless, Wheeler Trigg Kennedy LLP, Denver, Colorado, with him on the briefs), for Plaintiffs-Appellants.

John S. Koppel, Appellate Staff Civil Division (Peter D. Keisler, Assistant Attorney General, William J. Leone, United States Attorney, and William Kanter, Appellate Staff Civil Division, Washington, D.C., with him on the brief), for Defendants-Appellees.

Eric M. Lieberman and David B. Goldstein, Rabinowitz, Boudin, Standard, Krinsky & Lieberman, P.C., New York, New York, filed an Amicus Curiae brief in support of Defendants-Appellees.

Before HENRY, BRISCOE, and LUCERO, Circuit Judges.

HENRY, Circuit Judge.

Plaintiffs in this case range from orchestra conductors, educators, performers, and publishers to film archivists and motion picture distributors. They challenge two acts of Congress, the Copyright Term Extension Act ("CTEA"), Pub. L. No. 105-298, §§ 102(b) and (d), 112 Stat. 2827-28 (1998) (amending 17 U.S.C. §§ 302, 304), and § 514 of the Uruguay Round Agreements Act ("URAA"), Pub. L. No. 103-465, 108 Stat. 4809, 4976-80 (1994), codified at 17 U.S.C. §§ 104A, 1109.

2

Also known as the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act, the CTEA increased the duration of existing and future copyrights from life-plus-50-years to life-plus-70-years. Section 514 of the URAA implements Article 18 of the Berne Convention for the Protection of Literary and Artistic works. Ushered into being in 1886 at the behest of Association Littéraire et Artistique Internationale, an organization founded by Victor Hugo and dedicated to obtaining protection for literary and artistic works, the Berne Convention requires member countries to afford the same copyright protection to foreign authors as they provide their own authors. In this case, congressional compliance with the Berne Convention meant

3

copyrighting some foreign works in the public domain.

Plaintiffs argue the CTEA extends existing copyrights in violation of the "limited Times" provision of the Constitution's Copyright Clause. With regard to the URAA, plaintiffs contend § 514 shrinks the public domain and thereby violates the limitations on congressional power inherent in the Copyright Clause. In addition, plaintiffs argue that § 514's removal of works from the public domain interferes with their First Amendment right to free expression.

The district court dismissed plaintiffs' CTEA claim and granted summary judgment for the government on plaintiffs' URAA challenges. We exercise jurisdiction pursuant to 28 U.S.C. § 1291 and affirm the district court's dismissal of the CTEA claim as foreclosed by the Supreme Court's decision in Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186 (2003). We also agree with the district court that § 514 of the URAA has not exceeded the limitations inherent in the Copyright Clause. Nevertheless, we hold that plaintiffs have shown sufficient free expression interests in works removed from the public domain to require First Amendment

4

scrutiny of §514. On this limited basis, we remand for proceedings consistent with this opinion.

I. BACKGROUND

Each plaintiff in this case relies on artistic works in the public domain for his or her livelihood. Lawrence Golan, for example, performs and teaches works by foreign composers including Dmitri Shostakovich and Igor Stravinsky. Before the CTEA, plaintiffs anticipated that certain works would soon outlive copyright protection and enter the public domain. The CTEA delayed this moment by 20 years. Prior to the URAA, each plaintiff utilized or performed works by foreign artists in the public domain, such as Sergei Prokofiev's renowned "Peter and the Wolf." Since the passage of the URAA, plaintiffs must pay higher performance fees and sheet music rentals as well as other royalties. In many cases, these costs are prohibitive.

Plaintiffs filed suit in the United States District Court for the District of Colorado arguing that both the CTEA and the URAA are unconstitutional. The court concluded the Supreme Court's decision in Eldred precluded plaintiffs' challenge to the CTEA and granted summary judgment to the government on plaintiffs' two URAA claims.Golan v. Ashcroft, 310 F. Supp. 2d 1215, 1218 (D. Colo. 2004). Reasoning that "Congress has historically demonstrated little compunction about removing copyrightable materials from the public domain," the district court ruled that Congress had the power to enact § 514 of the URAA under

5

The Copyright Clause. Golan v. Gonzales, No. Civ. 01-1854 (BNB), 2005 WL 914754, at *14 (D. Colo. Aug. 24, 2005). The court also granted summary judgment on plaintiffs' First Amendment claim, on the theory they had no protected interest in the now-copyrighted works. This appeal followed.

II. STANDARD OF REVIEW

We review de novo a district court's grant of summary judgment. Steffy v. Orman, 461 F.3d 1218, 1221 (10th Cir. 2006). Summary judgment is appropriate only when "there is no genuine issue as to any material fact." FED. R. CIV. P. 56(c). We also examine de novo the district court's conclusions regarding the Constitution. O'Connor v. Washburn Univ., 416 F.3d 1216, 1223 (10th Cir. 2005). "[I]t is also appropriate to bear in mind . . . that in the enactment of a statute Congress is presumed to act with knowledge of controlling constitutional limitations or proscriptions and with an intent and purpose to avoid their contravention." Wells, by Gillig, v. Att'y General of the United States, 201 F.2d 556, 560 (10th Cir. 1953); see also INS v. Chadha, 462 U.S. 919, 944 (1983) ("We begin . . . with the presumption that the challenged statute is valid.").

III. DISCUSSION

Plaintiffs claim that the CTEA's 20-year extension of existing copyrights violates the Copyright Clause's "limited Times" provision. In addition, they contend that the URAA's removal of works from the public domain exceeds the authority granted to Congress under the Copyright Clause. Finally, plaintiffs

6

maintain that § 514 of the URAA must be subject to First Amendment review because it has altered the traditional contours of copyright protection. Since familiarity with the foundations of copyright law is crucial to understanding the dispute, we begin with an outline of basic copyright principles.

Under the Copyright Clause, Congress may "promote the Progress of Science and useful Arts, by securing for limited Times to Authors . . . the exclusive Right to their Writings." U.S. Const. art. I, § 8, cl. 8. The Supreme Court has explained that "[the Clause] is intended to motivate the creative activity of authors and inventors by the provision of a special reward, and to allow the public access to the products of their genius after the limited period of exclusive control has expired." Sony Corp. of Am. v. Universal City Studios, Inc., 464 U.S. 417, 429 (1984). By encouraging creative expression through limited monopolies, the Copyright Clause "promot[es] broad public availability of literature, music, and the other arts." Twentieth Century Music Corp. v. Aiken, 422 U.S. 151, 156 (1975). "[O]nce the . . . copyright monopoly has expired, the public may use the . . . work at will and without attribution." Dastar Corp. v. Twentieth Century Fox Film Corp., 539 U.S. 23, 33-34 (2003). These imaginative works inspire new creations, which in turn inspire others, hopefully, ad infinitum. This cycle is what makes copyright "the engine of free expression." Harper & Row Publishers Inc. v. Nation Enters., 471 U.S. 539, 558 (1985).

Congress's power to bestow copyrights is broad. See Eldred, 537 U.S. at

7

205 ("[I]t is Congress that has been assigned the task of defining the scope of the limited monopoly that should be granted to authors . . . in order to give the public appropriate access to their work product.") (internal quotation marks omitted). But it is not boundless. The Copyright Clause itself limits Congress's power as to what kinds of works can be copyrighted and for how long. For instance, in order to be copyrightable, a work must be original. Feist Publ'ns, Inc. v. Rural Tel. Serv. Co., 499 U.S. 340, 345 (1991) ("The sine qua non of copyright is originality . . . . Originality is a constitutional requirement."). In addition, a copyright must be limited in duration. Dastar, 539 U.S. at 37 (noting that Congress cannot "create[] a species of perpetual . . . copyright"). The rationale underlying this limitation is that an infinite copyright would deprive the public of the benefit -- the right to use and enjoy the expression -- that it is supposed to receive in exchange for the grant of monopoly privileges to the author for a discrete period of time. See id. at 33-34 ("The rights of a . . . copyright holder are part of a carefully crafted bargain under which, once the . . . copyright monopoly has expired, the public may use the . . . work at will and without attribution.") (internal citation and quotation marks omitted).

The Supreme Court has recognized that the First Amendment can limit Congress's power under the Copyright Clause. Eldred, 537 U.S. at 219-21 (indicating that copyright acts are not "categorically immune from challenges under the First Amendment") (internal quotation marks omitted). The Court has

8

emphasized, however, that "copyright's built-in First Amendment accommodations" -- the idea/expression dichotomy and the fair use defense -- generally protect the public's First Amendment interest in copyrighted works. Id. at 219-20.

The first of these "built-in safeguards," the idea/expression dichotomy, denies copyright protection "to any idea, procedure, process, system, method of operation, concept, principle, or discovery, regardless of the form in which it is described, explained, illustrated, or embodied in [a copyrighted] work." 17 U.S.C. § 102(b). It reserves to authors, however, the right to exploit their "expression," id., a term that refers to "the particular pattern of words, lines and colors, or musical notes" that comprise a work. ROBERT A. GORMAN, COPYRIGHT LAW 23 (2d ed. 2006).

The second safeguard, the fair use defense, allows the public to utilize a copyrighted work "for purposes such as criticism, comment, news reporting, teaching (including multiple copies for classroom use), scholarship, or research." 17 U.S.C. § 107. The defense protects the public's First Amendment interest in an author's original expression by "afford[ing] considerable latitude for scholarship and comment, and even for parody." Eldred, 537 U.S. at 220 (internal citations and quotation marks omitted).

Although these built-in free speech safeguards will ordinarily insulate legislation from First Amendment review, the Eldred Court indicated that such

9

review is warranted when an act of Congress has "altered the traditional contours of copyright protection." Id. at 221. The Court did not define the "traditional contours of copyright protection." However, as we discuss in detail below, one of these traditional contours is the principle that once a work enters the public domain, no individual not even the creator may copyright it.

With these principles in mind, we turn to plaintiffs' challenges to the CTEA and URAA.

A. THE CTEA

The Copyright Clause provides: "The Congress shall have Power . . . To promote the Progress of Science and useful Arts, by securing for limited Times to Authors and Inventors the exclusive Right to their respective Writings and Discoveries[.]" U.S. Const., art. I, § 8, cl. 8. Plaintiffs contend the CTEA violates the "limited Times" prescription by increasing the term from life-plus-50-years to life-plus-70-years. More specifically, they argue that "the Framers would have considered the [life-plus-70] term to be so long as to be effectively perpetual." Aplts' Br. at 55.

Analyzing the CTEA in light of the Clause's inherent limitations, the Supreme Court upheld the Act in Eldred. 537 U.S. at 194 ("[W]e reject petitioners' challenges to the CTEA. . . . Congress acted within its authority and did not transgress constitutional limitations."). Nevertheless, plaintiffs attempt to distinguish Eldred, invoking the Court's acknowledgment that "[p]etitioners [did]

10

not challenge the 'life-plus-70-years' timespan itself." Id. at 193. Plaintiffs therefore contend that Eldred does not foreclose the argument that the CTEA's extension of all future copyrights to a life-plus-70-years timespan violates the Copyright Clause. Though plaintiffs may be correct that the Eldred Court did not technically address this term, the rationale underlying Eldred compels us to conclude that the CTEA-imposed timespan passes constitutional muster.

The Ninth Circuit recently upheld the dismissal of a nearly-identical CTEA challenge in Kahle v. Gonzales, 487 F.3d 697 (9th Cir. 2007). The plaintiffs in Kahle, like plaintiffs here, argued that the CTEA's life-plus-70-years copyright term violated the "limited Times" prescription because the Framers would have viewed it as "effectively perpetual." Id. at 699 (internal quotation marks omitted). As the Ninth Circuit observed, the Eldred Court "clearly grasped the role 'limited Times' play in the copyright scheme and the Framers' understanding of that phrase." Id. at 700. Indeed, the Eldred Court emphasized that our constitutional scheme charges Congress, and not federal courts, with "the task of defining the scope of the limited monopoly that should be granted to authors." 537 U.S. at 205 (internal quotation marks omitted). As the Kahle court reasoned, "the outer boundary of 'limited Times' is determined by weighing the impetus provided to authors by longer terms against the benefit provided to the public by shorter terms. That weighing is left to Congress, subject to rationality review." Kahle, 487 F.3d at 701. This rationale is clearly consistent with Eldred. See 537 U.S. at 204

11

(reviewing the CTEA merely to determine "whether it is a rational exercise of the legislative authority conferred by the copyright clause").

We agree with the Kahle court's holding that Eldred precludes a challenge to the 20-year term extension. See Eldred, 537 U.S. at 208 ("We cannot conclude that the CTEA which continues the unbroken congressional practice of treating future and existing copyrights in parity for term extension purposes is an impermissible exercise of Congress' power under the Copyright Clause."). Plaintiffs here, like the plaintiffs in Kahle, "provide no compelling reason why we should depart from a recent Supreme Court decision." Kahle, 487 F.3d at 701.

B. THE URAA

Plaintiffs present two arguments regarding the constitutionality of § 514 of the URAA. First, they claim that § 514 exceeds the authority granted to Congress in the Copyright Clause. Second, they maintain § 514 has disrupted the traditional contours of copyright protection and thus demands First Amendment scrutiny. We begin with the contention that Congress has overstepped its Article I authority.

1. Section 514 does not violate the Copyright Clause

Plaintiffs ground their argument that § 514 transgresses the bounds of Congress's Article I authority in the text of the Copyright Clause. They contend that § 514's extension of copyright protection to works in the public domain eviscerates any limitations imposed by the "limited Times" prescription and the Progress Clause. In essence, plaintiffs aver that unless we hold that the Progress

12

Clause and the "limited Times" prescription prevent Congress from copyrighting works in the public domain, Congress could adopt a practice of copyrighting works as they fall into public domain. This would prevent the public from ever gaining unfettered access to the expressions.

We agree it would be troubling if Congress adopted a consistent practice of restoring works in the public domain in an effort to confer perpetual monopolies. But this argument is similar to one the Eldred plaintiffs raised, and, like the Eldred Court, we are mindful that "a regime of perpetual copyrights is clearly not the situation before us." Eldred, 537 U.S. at 209.

Plaintiffs cite Graham v. John Deere Co., 383 U.S.1 (1966), in support of their contentions. There, the Supreme Court concluded that Congress could not issue a patent when the invention had resided in the public domain before the inventor had applied for the patent. For both their Progress Clause and "limited Times" arguments, plaintiffs rely heavily on the Graham Court's statement that "Congress may not authorize the issuance of patents whose effects are to remove existent knowledge from the public domain, or to restrict free access to materials already available." Id. at 6. Plaintiffs contend there is no meaningful distinction between copyrights and patents that would prevent this court from applying Graham here.

The D.C. Circuit confronted and rejected an identical argument in Luck's Music Library, Inc. v. Gonzales, 407 F.3d 1262 (D.C. Cir. 2005), a case in which

13

the plaintiff maintained that § 514's copyright of works in the public domain violated the Copyright Clause. In rejecting the contention, the D.C. Circuit noted that
[Graham] dealt with patents rather than copyright, and the ideas applicable to one do [not] automatically apply to the other. For example, the Eldred Court saw the 'quid pro quo' idea as having a special force in patent law, where the patentee, in exchange for exclusive rights must disclose his 'discoveries' against his presumed will. In contrast, the author is eager to disclose her work.
407 F.3d at 1266.

In addition to these distinctions, the Eldred Court observed that while patents "prevent full use by others of the inventor's knowledge," "copyright gives the holder no monopoly on any knowledge." 537 U.S. at 217. We further note that the language plaintiffs cite from Graham is taken from a discussion about the Progress Clause in the context of conditions for patentability. The sentence following the one plaintiffs emphasize reads: "Innovation, advancement, and things which add to the sum of useful knowledge are inherent requisites in a patent system which by constitutional command must 'promote the Progress of . . . the useful Arts.'" Graham, 383 U.S. at 6 (emphasis supplied). In fact, the Graham Court only mentioned copyright in a footnote when it explained that it had omitted the copyright portion of the Patent and Copyright Clause because it was "not relevant" to the disposition of the case. Id. at 6 n.1. Thus, we conclude that plaintiffs have thrust onto Graham a burden it was never intended to bear. We

14

decline to read Graham as standing for the proposition that, in the context of copyright, the public domain is a threshold that Congress may not "traverse in both directions." Aplts' Br. at 50.

Furthermore, the Graham Court emphasized that the Constitution assigns Congress the task of "implement[ing] the stated purpose of the Framers by selecting the policy which in its judgment best effectuates the constitutional aim." 383 U.S. at 6. As discussed above, the Eldred Court echoed this refrain. See Eldred, 537 U.S. at 205 ("[I]t is Congress that has been assigned the task of defining the scope of the limited monopoly that should be granted to authors . . . in order to give the public appropriate access to their work product.") (internal quotation marks omitted). The clear import of Eldred is that Congress has expansive powers when it legislates under the Copyright Clause, and this court may not interfere so long as Congress has rationally exercised its authority. See Eldred, 237 U.S. at 213 (searching for a "rational basis for the conclusion that the CTEA 'Promotes the Progress of Science'"). Here, we do not believe that the decision to comply with the Berne Convention, which secures copyright protections for American works abroad, is so irrational or so unrelated to the aims of the Copyright Clause that it exceeds the reach of congressional power. Id. at 208 (emphasizing that the Court was "not at liberty to second-guess congressional determinations and policy judgments of this order, however debatable or arguably unwise they may be").

15

Nevertheless, legislation promulgated pursuant to the Copyright Clause must still comport with other express limitations of the Constitution. Saenz v. Roe, 526 U .S. 489, 508 (1999) ("Article I of the Constitution grants Congress broad power to legislate in certain areas. Those legislative powers are, however, limited not only by the scope of the Framers' affirmative delegation, but also by the principle that they may not be exercised in a way that violates other specific provisions of the Constitution.") (internal quotation marks omitted); Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U.S. 1, 132 (1976) ("Congress has plenary authority in all areas in which it has substantive legislative jurisdiction so long as the exercise of that authority does not offend some other constitutional restriction.") (internal citation omitted). Thus, even if Congress has not exceeded its Article I authority, § 514 may still be subject to First Amendment review.

2. Congress's Removal of Works from the Public Domain Alters the
Traditional Contours of Copyright Protection and Requires First
Amendment Scrutiny

We begin our First Amendment analysis by examining the intersection of the Copyright Clause and the First Amendment. In doing so, we address the Eldred Court's holding that the CTEA's extension of existing copyrights did not require First Amendment scrutiny and discuss the Court's suggestion that an act of Congress would only be subject to First Amendment review if it "altered the traditional contours of copyright protection." 537 U.S. at 221. Based on the Eldred Court's analysis, we examine the bedrock principle of copyright law that

16

works in the public domain remain there and conclude that § 514 alters the traditional contours of copyright protection by deviating from this principle. We then explain how this deviation implicates plaintiffs' First Amendment interest in the works at issue and determine that copyright's two built-in free speech safeguards the idea/expression dichotomy and the fair use defense do not adequately protect the First Amendment interests. Finally, we note that, unlike the CTEA, the URAA does not adopt supplemental free speech safeguards.

a. The Copyright Clause & the First Amendment

It is clear that the Copyright Clause is meant to foster values enshrined in the First Amendment. See Harper & Row, 471 U.S. at 558 (observing that "the Framers intended copyright itself to be the engine of free expression"). The Clause's primary purpose is to provide authors with incentives to produce works that will benefit the public. See id. at 546 ("The monopoly created by copyright thus rewards the individual author in order to benefit the public.") (internal quotation marks omitted) (emphasis supplied); Aiken, 422 U.S. at 156 ("The immediate effect of our copyright law is to secure a fair return for an 'author's' creative labor. But the ultimate aim is, by this incentive, to stimulate artistic creativity for the general public good.") (emphasis supplied); Mazer v. Stein, 347 U.S. 201, 219 (1954) ("The economic philosophy behind the clause empowering Congress to grant [] copyrights is the conviction that encouragement of individual effort by personal gain is the best way to advance public welfare through the

17

talents of authors ... in '...[the] useful Arts.'")' Fox Film Corp. v. Doyal, 286 U.S. 123, 127 (1932) ("The sole interest of the United States and the primary object in conferring the monopoly lie in the general benefits derived by the public from the labors of authors.").

In Eldred, the connection between the First Amendment and copyright prompted the Court to reject the proposition that "copyrights [are] categorically immune from challenges under the First Amendment." 537 U.S. at 221 (internal quotation marks omitted). However, under the facts of Eldred, copyright's inherent free speech protections obviated any need for First Amendment review of the CTEA. The Court based this holding on three factors. First, the Court concluded that copyright law's "built-in First Amendment accommodations" the idea/expression dichotomy and fair use defense adequately protected the First Amendment interests at stake. Id. at 219. Second, the Court reasoned that the plaintiffs had only a trivial interest in the copyrighted works because "[t]he First Amendment securely protects the freedom to make or decline to make one's own speech; it bears less heavily when speakers assert the right to make other people's speeches." Id. at 221 (emphasis supplied). Finally, the Court noted that the CTEA provided supplemental protections to ensure that the Act did not diminish the public's access to protected expression. Id. at 220. The Court further indicated that legislation could be subject to First Amendment scrutiny if it "altered the traditional contours of copyright protection." Id. at 221.

18

b. The principle that works in the public domain remain there is a
traditional contour of copyright protection that § 514 alters

We begin our analysis of § 514 by exploring the traditional contours of copyright protection. The Eldred Court did not define the "traditional contours of copyright protection," and we do not find, nor do the parties suggest that the phrase appears in any other federal authority that might shed light on its meaning. Nevertheless, the term seems to refer to something broader than copyright's built-in free speech accommodations.

Our understanding of the traditional contours of copyright protection has both a functional and a historical component. With regard to the functional aspect, we note that a contour is "an outline" or "the general form or structure of something." WEBSTER'S NINTH NEW COLLEGIATE DICTIONARY 284 (1984). Because the term copyright refers to a process as well as a form of intellectual property rights, we assess whether removing a work from the public domain alters the ordinary procedure of copyright protection. Relatedly, we explore the way in which the public domain delimits the scope of copyright protection. In addition, the Eldred Court's use of the word "traditional" to modify "contours" suggests that Congress's historical practice with respect to copyright and the public domain must inform our inquiry. Based on these criteria, we conclude that the traditional contours of copyright protection include the principle that works in the public domain remain there and that § 514 transgresses this critical boundary.

19

i. Copyright Sequence

Although the specific requirements for perfecting a copyright have changed over the years, the process has always begun when an author generates an original expression. The 1909 Copyright Act required an author seeking protection to attach notice to any distributed copies of his or her work. Moreover, the author could not initiate an infringement action or apply for a renewal unless he or she had formally registered the work with the copyright office. The 1976 Act removed many of the consequences for failure to register or attach notice, and, in 1989, the United States effectively abandoned all formalities as a condition of compliance with the Berne Convention. Thus, today, a limited copyright attaches at the moment a work is created. 3 When the copyright expires at the end of the statutory period, the work becomes part of the public domain. Until § 514, every statutory scheme preserved the same sequence. A work progressed from 1) creation; 2) to copyright; 3) to the public domain. Under § 514, the copyright sequence no longer necessarily ends with the public domain: indeed, it may begin there. Thus, by copyrighting works in the public domain, the URAA has altered the ordinary copyright sequence.

ii. Public Domain

The significance of the copyright sequence, combined with the principle

20

that no individual may copyright a work in the public domain, is that ordinarily works in the public domain stay there. See Country Kids 'N City Slicks, Inc. v. Sheen, 77 F.3d 1280, 1287 (10th Cir. 1996) (holding that a doll design could not be copyrighted because it was characterized by "typical paper doll features found in the public domain"); Lipton v. Nature Co., 71 F.3d 464, 470 (2d Cir. 1995) ("[F]acts are considered to be in the public domain and therefore not protectable under copyright law . . . ."); Norma Ribbon & Trimming, Inc. v. Little, 51 F.3d 45, 48 (5th Cir. 1995) (holding that certain flowers could not be copyrighted "because these same flowers already existed in the public domain"); United States v. Hamilton, 583 F.2d 448, 450 (9th Cir. 1987) (noting that "a map which represents a new combination of information already in the public domain lacks any element worthy of copyright protection"); M.M. Bus. Forms Corp. v. Uarco, Inc., 472 F.2d 1137, 1140 (6th Cir. 1973) ("Elementary legal words and phrases are in the public domain and no citizen may gain monopoly thereover to the exclusion of their use by other citizens."); Amsterdam v. Triangle Publ'ns, Inc., 189 F.2d 104, 106 (3d Cir. 1951) ("The location of county lines, township lines and municipal lines is information within the public domain, and is not copyrightable."); Christianson v. West Pub. Co., 149 F.2d 202, 203 (9th Cir. 1945) ("The outline map of the United States with state boundaries is in the public domain and is not copyrightable.") (internal quotation marks omitted); Meade v. United States, 27 Fed. Cl. 367, 372 (1992) (holding that "defendant's LOVE stamp" could not be copyrighted because

21

it "exist[ed] in the public domain"); see also Toro Co. v. R&R Prods.Co., 787 F.2d 1208, 1213 (8th Cir. 1908) ("If the disputed work is similar to a pre-existing protected work or one in the public domain, the second work must contain some variation recognizable as that of the second author.").

In Sheldon v. Metro-Goldwyn Pictures Corp., 81 F.2d 49, 54 (2d Cir. 1936), aff'd, 309 U.S. 390, 392 (1940), Judge Learned Hand, a luminary in the field of copyright law, illustrated this principle when he stated that "if by some magic a man who had never known it were to compose anew Keats's Ode on a Grecian Urn, he would be an 'author,' and, if he copyrighted it, others might not copy that poem, though they might of course copy Keats." Sheldon, 81 F.2d at 54. As Judge Hand observed, Keats's poems remained in the public domain free for anyone to copy even if someone copyrighted the identical language. Section 514 contravenes this principle.

iii. The history of American copyright law reveals no tradition of
copyrighting works in the public domain

As we stated above, the fact that the Eldred Court used the word "traditional" to modify "contours" suggests that the history of American copyright law should inform our inquiry. Eldred, 537 U.S. at 221. Accordingly, we look for evidence indicating that the Framers believed removal of works from the public domain was consistent with the copyright scheme they designed. Congress's past practices are also pertinent to determining whether extricating works from the

22

public domain is a tradition of our country's copyright law.

a. The Framers' Views

Unfortunately, constitutional historians know little about the Framers' views regarding copyright and the public domain. In part, this is because, when the states ratified the Constitution, "the Common Law of the United States . . . was in a highly uncertain state on the subject of copyrights." 1 William W. Crosskey, POLITICS AND THE CONSTITUTION IN THE HISTORY OF THE UNITED STATES 477 (1953). Uncertainty also stems from the fact that none of the usual, reliable sources The Federalist Papers, Madison's notes from the Constitutional Convention, or accounts of the First Congress's deliberations take up the subject in any detail.

Passed in 1790, the first Copyright Act granted fourteen years of protection for books, maps, and charts already printed in the United States. See Eldred, 537 U.S. at 194 (discussing the 1790 Act). The parties debate whether the First Congress extended copyright protection to works already in the public domain. While the Eldred Court recognized that "the First Congress clearly did confer copyright protection on works that had already been created," id. at 196 n.3, plaintiffs argue convincingly that most, if not all, of these works were covered by a state common-law copyright and therefore not in the public domain. In response, the government observes that not all states enacted copyright statutes during the period of the Articles of Confederation. See Feltner v. Columbia

23

Pictures Television, Inc. 523 U.S. 340 (1998) (citing Copyright Enactments: Laws Passed in the United States Since 1783 Relating to Copyright 21 (Copyright Office ed., Bulletin No. 3, rev. 1963)); Thomas B. Nachbar, Intellectual Property and Constitutional Norms, 104 Colum. L. Rev. 272, 338 n.284(2004) ("Of the general copyright laws passed by the States during the years of the Articles of Confederation, two of them (Maryland and Pennsylvania) never even came into effect; they included reciprocity clauses that were never fulfilled because one State, Delaware, never enacted a general copyright law . . . .").

Although the history of the 1790 Act could be highly informative of the Framers' views, the answer to the question of whether Congress thought it was removing works from the public domain is probably not just unclear but also unknowable. Edward C. Walterscheid, Understanding the Copyright Act of 1790: the Issue of Common Law Copyright in America and the Modern Interpretation of the Copyright Power, 53 J. Copyright Soc'y U.S.A. 313, 332 (2006) ("There is very little contemporaneous legislative history dealing with the 1790 Act."); see also id. at 340 ("[I]t is impossible to demonstrate with any reasonable certainty from the language of the 1790 Copyright Act and the circumstances surrounding its enactment that Congress believed that it was creating a property right in authors rather than affirming and protecting an existing common-law right, albeit for a limited time.").

Given the scarcity of historical evidence, we cannot conclude that the

24

Framers viewed removal of works from the public domain as consistent with the copyright scheme they created. Nor do we discern at the dawn of the Republic any burgeoning tradition of removing works from the public domain.

b. Congressional Practice Since the First Congress

At oral argument, the government conceded that apart from the 1790 Act's purported grant of copyright protection to works in the public domain, there have been few instances of such grants since. It does, however, point to a series of private bills granting copyrights to individuals. But "[t]hese private bills do not support the [government's] historical gloss, but rather significantly undermine the historical claim." Eldred, 537 U.S. at 234 (Stevens, J., dissenting). Far from providing evidence that copyrighting works in the public domain is within the traditional contours of copyright protection, the fact that individuals were forced to resort to the uncommon tactic of petitioning Congress demonstrates that this practice was outside the normal practice.

In addition, the government argues that the wartime acts of Dec 18, 1919, Pub. L. No. 66-102, 41 Stat. 368, and the Emergency Copyright Act of 1941, Pub. L. No. 77-258, 55 Stat. 732, removed works from the public domain by granting the President authority to give foreign authors additional time to comply with copyright requirements. However, a review of the historical record reveals that these emergency wartime bills, passed in response to exigent circumstances, merely altered the means by which authors could comply with the procedural rules

25

for copyright; these bills were not explicit attempts to remove works from the public domain. The Emergency Copyright Act of 1941, for example, recognized that authors "may have been temporarily unable to comply with [copyright formalities] because of the disruption or suspension of facilities essential for such compliance." 55 Stat. 732 (emphasis supplied).

The statutory context of these acts reveals that they were, at most, a brief and limited departure from a practice of guarding the public domain. In previous actions granting copyrights to foreign authors, Congress emphasized that it was not attempting to interfere with the rights of Americans who had relied on the foreign works. For example, the 1919 Act stated that "nothing herein contained shall be construed to deprive any person of any right which he may have acquired by the republication of such foreign work in the United States prior to approval of this Act." 41 Stat. 369. One of the Acts to which the 1919 Act referred was the 1909 Copyright Act. That Act made clear that "no copyright shall subsist in the original text of any work which is in the public domain." Copyright Act, Pub. L. No. 60-349, 35 Stat. 1075, 1077 (1909) (emphasis supplied).

This context notwithstanding, the wartime acts may have had the effect of removing a very small number of works from the public domain. Nevertheless, this possibility is insufficient to establish a traditional contour of copyright law. Indeed, world war is (hopefully) not traditional. The fact that the legislation was passed in response to the exigencies of a world war suggests that Congress felt

26

compelled to depart from its normal practice of preserving the public domain. Moreover, the mere passage of these discrete acts does not indicate that such removal was consistent with any provision of the Constitution, including the First Amendment. See 3 NIMMER ON COPYRIGHT § 9A.07[A], 9A-79 to -80 (2007) (stating that "although three [wartime] enactments granted very limited resurrection, . . . the practice under those circumscribed enactments was simply to sweep the constitutional issues under the rug").

Based on the foregoing, we see no tradition of removing works from the public domain. Indeed, if anything, our examination of the history of American copyright law reveals that removal was the exception rather than the rule. Thus, § 514 deviates from the time-honored tradition of allowing works in the public domain to stay there.

iv. Conclusion

In sum, by extending a limited monopoly to expressions historically beyond the pale of such privileges, the URAA transformed the ordinary process of copyright protection and contravened a bedrock principle of copyright law that works in the public domain remain in the public domain. Therefore, under both the functional and historical components of our inquiry, § 514 has altered the traditional contours of copyright protection.

c. The URAA's removal of works from the public domain
implicates plaintiffs' First Amendment interest

27

We now explain how this alteration of traditional contours affects the First Amendment interests of these plaintiffs. To begin, as discussed above, copyright law bears out the rather obvious but significant point that works in the public domain belong to the public. See Dastar, 539 U.S. at 33-34 (2003) ("[O]nce the . . . copyright monopoly has expired, the public may use the . . . work at will and without attribution."); Am. Tobacco Co. v. Werckmeister, 207 U.S. 284, 299-300 (1907) (observing that widespread publication of a work without copyright protection "render[s] such work common property") (emphasis supplied). As Judge Hand made clear in National Comics Publications, Inc. v. Fawcett Publications, Inc., 171 F.2d 594, 603 (2d Cir. 1951), a case that involved copyrights to "Superman" and "Captain Marvel" comic strips, "once [the strips fell] into the public domain . . . anyone might copy them." In other words, each member of the public -- "anyone" -- has a non-exclusive right, subject to constitutionally permissible legislation, to use material in the public domain. The implication of this principle is that the plaintiffs here possessed a non-exclusive right to use the works at issue.

Furthermore, the First Amendment protects plaintiffs' right to unrestrained artistic use of these works. The Supreme Court has emphasized that the right to artistic expression is near the core of the First Amendment. Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U.S. 781, 790 (1989) ("Music is one of the oldest forms of human expression. From Plato's discourse in the Republic to the totalitarian state in our

28

own times, rulers have known [music's] capacity to appeal to the intellect and to the emotions, and have censored musical compositions to serve the needs of the state. . . . The Constitution prohibits any like attempts in our own legal order. Music, as a form of expression and communication, is protected under the First Amendment."); Schad v. Borough of Mount Ephraim, 452 U.S. 61, 65 (1981) ("Entertainment, as well as political and ideological speech, is protected; motion pictures, programs broadcast by radio and television, and live entertainment, such as musical and dramatic works, fall within the First Amendment guarantee."); Kaplan v. California, 413 U .S. 115, 119-120 (1973) ("[P]ictures, films, paintings, drawings, and engravings . . . have First Amendment protection . . . .").

Together, the clear import of these principles is that the public in general and these plaintiffs in particular have a First Amendment interest in using works in the public domain. For example, at the moment that Dmitri Shostakovich's Symphony No. 5 entered the public domain, Plaintiff John Blackburn had a right to create a derivative work for a high school band to perform at an event commemorating 9/11. The principle of copyright law that shields works in the public domain from copyright ensured Mr. Blackburn's right to create the piece, and the First Amendment protected his right to perform it.

Section 514 has interfered with Mr. Blackburn's right by making the cost of performance or creation of new derivative works based on Shostakovich's Symphony No. 5 prohibitive. Moreover, as the example of Mr. Blackburn's

29

composition suggests, plaintiffs' First Amendment interests in public domain works are greater than the interests of the Eldred plaintiffs. The Eldred plaintiffs did not -- nor had they ever -- possessed unfettered access to any of the works at issue there. As the Eldred Court observed, the most the Eldred plaintiffs could show was a weak interest in "making other people's speeches." 537 U.S. 221. By contrast, the speech at issue here belonged to plaintiffs when it entered the public domain. In reliance on their rights to these works, plaintiffs have already performed or planned future performances and used these publically available works to create their own artistic productions. 4

By removing works from the public domain, § 514 arguably hampers free expression and undermines the values the public domain is designed to protect. See Meade, 27 Fed. Cl. at 372 ("Extending copyright protection to a heart-shaped picture of earth effectively would grant the copyright holder a monopoly over the innumerable ways of expressing this picture. Allowing this picture to remain in the public domain for all artists to interpret freely, however, will foster creativity

30

by ensuring that future mapmakers and artists have an ample store of ideas on which to build their works."). We therefore conclude that once the works at issue became free for anyone to copy, plaintiffs in this case had vested First Amendment interests in the expressions, and § 514's interference with plaintiffs' rights is subject to First Amendment scrutiny.

f. Copyright's built-in free speech safeguards are not adequate to
protect the First Amendment interests at stake

In Eldred, the Court indicated that "copyright's built-in free speech safeguards are generally adequate to address [First Amendment concerns]." 537 U.S. at 221 (emphasis supplied). Below, we conclude that the idea/expression dichotomy and the fair use defense are not designed to combat the threat to free expression posed by § 514's removal of works from the public domain.

i. Idea/Expression Dichotomy

The idea/expression dichotomy protects First Amendment interests by ensuring that "no author may copyright facts or ideas. The copyright is limited to those aspects of the work termed `expression' that display the stamp of the author's originality." Harper & Row, 471 U.S. at 547 (citation omitted). The Supreme Court has observed that the idea/expression dichotomy "strikes a definitional balance between the First Amendment and the Copyright Act by permitting free communication of facts while still protecting an author's expression." Eldred, 537 U.S. at 219 (quoting Harper, 471 U.S. at 556). See 4

31

NIMMER ON COPYRIGHT, supra, §19E.03[A][2], at 19E-20 to -21 ("In general, the democratic dialogue a self-governing people's participation in the marketplace of ideas is adequately served if the public has access to an author's ideas, and such loss to the dialogue as results from inaccessibility to an author's 'expression' is counterbalanced by the greater public interest in the copyright system.").

However, the idea/expression dichotomy's utility as a definitional mechanism is limited to determining whether a proposed work is an idea or whether the work displays sufficient originality to constitute an expression. In the typical case, the danger to free speech interests is that an individual might gain monopoly privileges over an idea. Here, by contrast, there is no doubt that the works at issue are expressions; the threat to free expression lies not in what is being copyrighted, but in the fact that the works are being removed from the public domain. The idea/expression dichotomy is simply not designed to determine whether Congress's grant of a limited monopoly over an expression in the public domain runs afoul of the First Amendment.

ii. Fair Use Defense

"The [fair use] defense provides: the fair use of a copyrighted work, including such use by reproduction in copies . . . , for purposes such as criticism, comment, news reporting, teaching (including multiple copies for classroom use), scholarship, or research, is not an infringement of copyright." 17 U.S.C. § 107 (internal quotation marks omitted). "[It] allows the public to use not only facts

32

and ideas contained in a copyrighted work, but also expression itself in certain circumstances." Eldred, 537 U.S. at 219. For example, although Ralph Ellison's estate may retain the copyright to his classic novel Invisible Man, the fair use defense permits scholars and teachers to quote extensively from the book and even reproduce entire sections for the purpose of commenting on (say) the parallels between the narrator's literal and figurative vision. Because the purpose of the fair use defense is to "afford[] considerable 'latitude for scholarship and comment,'" Eldred, 537 U.S. at 220 (quoting Harper, 471 U.S. at 560), the Court has described it as a "guarantee of breathing space within the confines of copyright." Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc., 510 U.S. 569, 579 (1994).

In our view, the fair use doctrine is not a sufficient safeguard of plaintiffs' First Amendment interests. Although the doctrine allows limited use of copyrighted works, it does not address works that have entered the public domain and are therefore available for unrestricted use. By withdrawing works from the public domain, § 514 leaves scholars, artists, and the public with less access to works than they had before the Act. The fact that the fair use doctrine permits some access to those works may not be an adequate substitute for the unlimited access enjoyed before the URAA was enacted. Thus, instead of providing additional "breathing space" for free expression, the fair use defense suggests that § 514 infringes upon plaintiffs' First Amendment rights.

In sum, "copyright's built-in free speech safeguards," Eldred, 537 U.S. at

33

221, are designed to govern the distribution of rights between authors and the public from the moment a work is created and copyrighted until the copyright expires. This design presumes that some rights are properly reserved for the author who has never relinquished his right to exploitation. Once a work has entered the public domain, however, neither the author nor the author's estate possesses any more right to the work than any member of the general public. Because § 514 bestows copyrights upon works in the public domain, these built-in safeguards are not adequate to protect plaintiffs' First Amendment interests.

iii. The URAA does not supplement the traditional First
Amendment safeguards

In concluding that the CTEA did not require First Amendment scrutiny, the Eldred Court noted that "the CTEA [] supplements the[] traditional safeguards." Id. The Court described the additional protections as follows:

First, [the CTEA] allows libraries, archives, and similar institutions to "reproduce" and "distribute, display, or perform in facsimile or digital form" copies of certain published works "during the last 20 years of any term of copyright . . . for purposes of preservation, scholarship, or research" if the work is not already being exploited commercially and further copies are unavailable at a reasonable price. 17 U.S.C. § 108(h). Second, Title II of the CTEA, known as the Fairness in Music Licensing Act of 1998, exempts small businesses, restaurants, and like entities from having to pay performance royalties on music played from licensed radio, television, and similar facilities.
Id. at 220 (quoting 17 U.S.C. § 108(h)) (some internal citations omitted).

The URAA contains none of the CTEA's supplemental First Amendment protections. It neither provides exceptions for "libraries, archives and similar

34

institutions," nor exemptions for "small businesses, restaurants and like entities from having to pay performance royalties." 17 U.S.C. § 108(h). Rather than excepting parties, such as plaintiffs, who have relied upon works in the public domain, the URAA provides only a safe harbor allowing a party to use a restored work for one year after receiving notice of the restored copyright protection. 17 U.S.C. § 104A(d)(2). We note, however, that it does permit a party to continue to use a work if notice is not given. See Luck's Music, 467 F.3d at 1265 (discussing § 104A(d)(2)). When compared to the CTEA, this is hardly a "guarantee of breathing space." Campbell, 510 U.S. at 579.

IV. INSTRUCTIONS FOR REMAND

In conducting its First Amendment analysis on remand, the district court should assess whether § 514 is content-based or content-neutral. Content-based restrictions on speech are those which "suppress, disadvantage, or impose differential burdens upon speech because of its content." Grace United Methodist Church v. City of Cheyenne, 451 F.3d 643, 657 (10th Cir. 2006) (internal citations and quotations omitted). These restrictions "are subject to the most exacting scrutiny." Id. If § 514 is a content-based restriction, then the district court will need to consider whether the government's interest in promulgating the legislation is truly "compelling" and whether the government might achieve the same ends

35

through alternative means that have less of an effect on protected expression. 5 United States v. Playboy Entm't Group, Inc., 529 U.S. 803, 813 (2000). By contrast, "[a] regulation that serves purposes unrelated to the content of expression is deemed neutral, even if it has an incidental effect on some speakers or messages but not others." Rock Against Racism, 491 U.S. at 791. A content-neutral restriction must be "narrowly tailored to serve a significant governmental interest." Id. (quoting Clark v. Cmty. for Creative Non-Violence, 468 U.S. 288, 293 (1984)).

36

V. CONCLUSION

For the foregoing reasons, we affirm the district court's dismissal of the CTEA claim as foreclosed by Eldred. We also affirm the district court's holding that § 514 of the URAA does not exceed the limitations inherent in the Copyright Clause. Nevertheless, since § 514 has altered the traditional contours of copyright protection in a manner that implicates plaintiffs' right to free expression, it must be subject to First Amendment review. We therefore REMAND for proceedings consistent with this opinion.

37

1 Section 104A provides in the pertinent part:

(a) Automatic protection and term. --
(1) Term.
(A) Copyright subsists, in accordance with this section, in restored works, and vests automatically on the date of restoration....

(h) Definitions. For purposes of this section and section 109(a): ...

(6) The term "restored work" means an original work of authorship that --
(A) is protected under subsection (a);
(B) is not in the public domain in its source country through expiration of term of protection;
(C) is in the public domain in the United States due to --

(I) noncompliance with formalities imposed at any time by United States copyright law, including failure of renewal, lack of proper notice, or failure to comply with any manufacturing requirements; (ii) lack of subject matter protection in the case of sound recordings fixed before February 15, 1972; or (iii) lack of national eligibility; and
(D) has at least one author or rightholder who was, at the time the work was created, a national or domiciliary of an eligible country, and if published was first published in an eligible country and not published in the United States during the 30-day period following publication in such eligible country.

2 Article 18 of the Berne Convention provides in the pertinent part:

(1) This Convention shall apply to all works which, at the moment of its coming into force, have not yet fallen into the public domain in the country of origin through the expiry of the term of protection.
(2) If, however, through the expiry of the term of protection which was previously granted, a work has fallen into the public domain, of the country where the protection is claimed, that work shall not be protected anew [.]

3 An author must still include notice in order to defend against "innocent infringer[s]." GORMAN, supra, at 91.

4 Interestingly, during the Eldred oral argument, Justice Souter asked then-Solicitor General Olsen whether the Copyright Clause combined with the Necessary and Proper Clause could justify the extension of monopoly privileges to a "copyright that expired yesterday." Aplts' Supp. Auth. dated June 2, 2006, Transcript of Oral Argument at 44, Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186 (No. 01-618). The Solicitor General replied that although such an act was not inconceivable, the public domain likely presented a "bright line" because once "[s]omething . . . has already gone into the public domain [] other individuals or companies or entities may then have acquired an interest in, or rights to be involved in disseminating [the work.]" Id.

5 Although not mentioned by the parties, Congress's treaty, commerce, and takings powers may provide Congress with the authority to enact § 514. See 3 NIMMER ON C OPYRIGHT § 9A.07[B], 9A-79 to -80, 90A.07[C], 9A-85. We also note that at oral argument, Professor Lessig claimed that the experience of other countries, such as the United Kingdom, suggests that the United States could comply with the Berne Convention through less restrictive means. Indeed, the United Kingdom Copyright Statute, as well as the statutes in Australia, Canada, India, and New Zealand, define a reliance party as any person who "incurs or has incurred any expenditure or liability in connection with, for the purpose of or with a view to the doing of an act which at the time is not or was not an act restricted by any copyright in the work." Irwin Karp, Final Report, Berne Article 18 Study on Retroactive United States Copyright Protection for Berne and Other Works, 20 COLUM.-VLA J.L. & Arts 157, 178 (Winter 1996) (quoting "The Copyright (Application to Other Countries) Order in Council 988"; June 13, 1989, Article 7(2), reprinted in Copyright Laws and Treaties of the World, UK: Item 7c, at 2 (Unesco Supp. 1989-1990). Under the British, Canadian, Australian, and Indian systems, "the reliance party is allowed to continue making those uses of the work it had made, or incurred commitments to make, before its copyright is restored. But the reliance party can be 'bought out' by the owner of the restored copyright. That is, the reliance party must cease exploiting the work if the owner pays compensation, in an amount to be determined by negotiation or arbitration." Id.


  


Fair Use: Affirmative Defense or Right? Do I Have to Choose? | 215 comments | Create New Account
Comments belong to whoever posts them. Please notify us of inappropriate comments.
Corrections here
Authored by: Erwan on Sunday, September 09 2007 @ 01:48 PM EDT
If any.

---
Erwan

[ Reply to This | # ]

OT, Off topic thread
Authored by: Erwan on Sunday, September 09 2007 @ 01:50 PM EDT
There's always plenty.

---
Erwan

[ Reply to This | # ]

News Picks discussion.
Authored by: Erwan on Sunday, September 09 2007 @ 01:51 PM EDT
[OT, and here's a hat trick. :-) ]

---
Erwan

[ Reply to This | # ]

Fair Use: Affirmative Defense or Right? Do I Have to Choose?
Authored by: billposer on Sunday, September 09 2007 @ 02:22 PM EDT

I think that it is wrong to present this as a dichotomy: it is perfectly possible for something to be both an affirmative defense and a right. An example is self-defense. As a defense to a homicide charge, self-defense is an affirmative defense. It is also a right.

An affirmative defense is simply a defense that does not negate one of the elements of the charge. The defense that "I didn't do it" is a non-affirmative defense because it negates one of the elements of the crime. Similarly, the defense that no killing occurred (if the body has not been found), or in a copyright case, that no copying in fact took place, is non-affirmative since the occurrence of a killing and of copying are essential elements of homicide and copyright infringement respectively. There is no relationship between the nature of a defense and whether it is a right.

When the Copyright Alliance claims that Fair Use is only an affirmative defense, not a right, they could mean either of two things. If they mean that Fair Use cannot be a right because it is an affirmative defense, they are flat out wrong, under existing law. There simply isn't any connection. If, however, they mean only that, "Yes, the statute makes Fair Use available as an affirmative defense, but that doesn't mean that Fair Use is a right", they are correct. Of course, that doesn't mean that it isn't a right either, and as PJ says, there is a colorable argument, one that I believe to be correct, that Fair Use is a right under the First Amendment. But if there is such a right, it stems from the First Amendment and not from the Fair Use provisions of the copyright statutes.

[ Reply to This | # ]

Fair Use: Do we have an equivalent in the UK or EU?
Authored by: SilverWave on Sunday, September 09 2007 @ 02:56 PM EDT
Fair Use in the US is obviously an important issue - but I wonder how this
affects the EU?

Anything equivalent in the UK or EU?

hmmmm...
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Fair_use#United_Kingdom

That looks like a no then :(

---
"intellectual property" - a propaganda term designed to confuse patent law with
copyright and other unrelated laws and to muddy the different issues they raise.

[ Reply to This | # ]

Fair Use according to section 107 of the US
Authored by: Anonymous on Sunday, September 09 2007 @ 03:00 PM EDT
PJ,

I give away a compilation of MIDI files. Since the information or file(s) are
being used as a teaching aid, I believe that myself, as well as the recipient of
the files, are protected under section 107. Here's the legal disclaimer I use.


LEGAL DISCLAIMER

Distribution of this content on this disk is controlled by section 107 of the US
Copyright code. From Sect. 107. Limitations on exclusive rights: fair use
"Notwithstanding the provisions of sections 106 and 106A [17 USCS Sects.
106, 106A], the fair use of a copyrighted work, including such use by
reproduction in copies or phonorecords or by any other means specified by that
section, for purposes such as criticism, comment, news reporting, teaching
(including multiple copies for classroom use), scholarship, or research, is not
an infringement of copyright. In determining whether the use made of a work in
any particular case is a fair use the factors to be considered shall
include"

(1) the purpose and character of the use, including whether such use is of a
commercial nature or is for nonprofit educational purposes;

(2) the nature of the copyrighted work;

(3) the amount and substantiality of the portion used in relation to the
copyrighted work as a whole; and

(4) the effect of the use upon the potential market for or value of the
copyrighted work.

Whether or not this would stand up in court is debatable. MIDI files do NOT
reproduce every nuance, or tonal characteristics of the original copyrighted
recording. They DO contain most of the notes in mostly the correct order
although in a different format that than found in typical music notation..

As you may know, MIDI files freely available on the Net have recently become the
target of the MPAA, RIAA and others. Most websites rather than go to court have
removed the files.


Anon46

[ Reply to This | # ]

Who is Patrick Ross and why should I care?
Authored by: Anonymous on Sunday, September 09 2007 @ 03:13 PM EDT
Obviously, this guy is a *well* paid shill for the RIAA and the MPAA. It doesn't
surprise me that he speaks ill of anything that implies first amendment rights
apply to anyone except his billionaire overlords.

[ Reply to This | # ]

Have I got this right?
Authored by: Anonymous on Sunday, September 09 2007 @ 03:22 PM EDT
If I have a right to do something, then someone else may not prevent me from
doing it. If someone prevents me from exercising that right then I have
recourse to the courts.

If I only have an affirmative defense, it only becomes effective if I get sued.
If someone prevents me from doing the action anticipated by the affirmative
defense, I do not have recourse to the courts.

In other words, if fair use is only an affirmative defense, DRM can prevent fair
use and there's nothing I can do about it. If fair use is a right then I can
sue someone if their DRM prevents me from exercising that right.

[ Reply to This | # ]

Fair Use: Affirmative Defense or Right? Do I Have to Choose?
Authored by: Anonymous on Sunday, September 09 2007 @ 03:32 PM EDT
I think that the only effective protection for digital works is going to end up
being watermarking the digital work and then maintaining records to tie the
watermark to a particular sale (and then advertising the fact that it's there to
discourage users from indiscriminate sharing)

this watermarking can be as blatant as Itunes has where they put info about who
purchased the tune inside each non-DRMd track they sell, or it could be a simple
number hidden inside the track (or a combination of these)

if people learn that posting tracks on the Internet can be tracked back to them
they will be less likely to do so.

yes, you will still have people claiming that their computer was hacked and
that's how the files got out, but you will always have some people breaking the
law, and the fact that people who have have acquired the tracks will know that
they can be identified as belonging to someone else will discourage them from
keeping them.

[ Reply to This | # ]

Publication and Copyright
Authored by: Simon G Best on Sunday, September 09 2007 @ 04:01 PM EDT

I think it might be helpful to consider the role of publication in this issue.

If an author abstains from publishing their work, then no one else gets to copy it at all. Is there some denial of fair use there? Does the first amendment compel authors to publish, lest the rest of us be unable to exercise Freedom of Speech in relation to the unpublished works? I would say that the right to Freedom of Speech includes the right not to publish - otherwise, so-called "Free Speech" wouldn't be a right but an obligation, and wouldn't be Free. Fair use obviously doesn't trump the right not to publish.

Without copyright, an author could disclose their work to those who agreed to enter into some kind of agreement with them, such as a Non-Disclosure Agreement (NDA). Such an NDA could work as a kind of private copyright. Those who choose to decline entry into such NDAs would not have the work disclosed to them. Those who do enter into such NDAs do then get to see the work, but have, by then, already agreed not to disclose it to others. Does or should fair use or Freedom of Speech trump such confidentiality? I don't believe so, and would be opposed to such confidentiality-trumping.

With copyright, the authors get to retain some such control despite publication. But what about those who would not wish to enter into, say, the aforementioned, hypothetical NDAs? Copyright law includes fair use, which, amongst other things, is supposed to keep copyright from infringing such rights as first amendment Free Speech rights.

When considering such things as DRM and fair use, I do think it's sensible to bear in mind the author's option of simply not publishing, or disclosing their work to only those who agree to such things as NDAs. But I need to eat before I get on to where this kind of thinking leads me when it comes to such things as DRM and the DMCA.

---
"Public relations" is a public relations term for propaganda.

[ Reply to This | # ]

"If I don't have Fair Use....
Authored by: Latesigner on Sunday, September 09 2007 @ 04:02 PM EDT
...You don't have Copyright." Spotted on /. I thought he was right at the time, it's agreement between the public and the creator, and now I know it.

---
The only way to have an "ownership" society is to make slaves of the rest of us.

[ Reply to This | # ]

Fair Use: Affirmative Defense or Right? Do I Have to Choose?
Authored by: Nomen Publicus on Sunday, September 09 2007 @ 04:08 PM EDT
"Fair use" is not some arbitrary bolt-on goody. It is essential for the normal operation of publishing in all forms of media.

If, for instance, a TV news program has to obtain clearance for every single clip before transmission, there would be no timely news reports -- all you would have is a costly history lesson.

The attack on "fair use" is very clever. It is a blatant attempt to steal the culture of an entire society under the guise of changing a very small part of copyright law.

If there is no "fair use" there are no critical reviews; if there is no "fair use" you can't use a politicians words against them; if there is no "fair use" most consumer rights become difficult to enforce.

---
If you love some code, set it free.

[ Reply to This | # ]

Fair Use: Affirmative Defense or Right? Do I Have to Choose?
Authored by: John Hasler on Sunday, September 09 2007 @ 04:18 PM EDT
> could DRM -- run afoul of the First Amendment if it makes
> all fair use impossible?

DRM cannot make all fair use impossible as you can always copy off the screen or
record from the speaker.

What sort of fair use requires a direct digital copy?

---
IOANAL. Licensed under the GNU General Public License

[ Reply to This | # ]

Several additional issues and questions
Authored by: Anonymous on Sunday, September 09 2007 @ 05:01 PM EDT
Very interesting article, PJ. I wonder though if there aren't other places and
ways that have already begun to alter the "traditional contours of
copyright protection".

The first is length of copyrights - they're now effectively perpetual. That is,
ALL works created in my lifetime are, by the sheer fact of expected lifespan,
inaccessible to me to build upon. That this was done through payoffs and
corruption is not the issue - that's a blight on Congress and the Senate - the
point is that there is simply ZERO chance for me or anybody else to ever expand
upon the works created in our lifetimes. This automatically reverts all
"new" innovation to be applicable to only that material created since
roughly 1923 - a horrendous step *backwards* in time, and thus violating the
premise of the Copryight laws regarding both the "limited time"
provision (there is no limit to the time for the authors - it exceeds their
lifetime too) and the intent of fostering innovation (effectively, all 7 billion
people alive today are precluded from innovating on any material created in the
past 90 years or so).

That's bad enough, but now add DRM which as you (correctly) noted is perpetual.
But there's another problem with DRM - it also restricts subsets and extractions
from a DRM'd work. So DRM violates not only the fair use provisions, but also
the full intent of copyright law including subsets. Arguing about 300 lines out
of 200,000 *directly* related to common historical knowledge, or 3 notes of a
riff in some other case, is absolute proof of the lunacy of the courts when it
comes to common sense. The courts cannot be counted on to police themselves
when it comes to common sense. Certainly Congress can't either - they even let
such factors drive "free trade" and other disasters (since not a
single member of Congress has ever, to my mind, properly defined "Free
Trade", I feel very comfortable making that comment, by the way). And
corporations rarely if ever even try.

How do we, The People, put an end to these monstrosities?

Combined with a very lopsided legal system which is quickly becoming a
playground for the rich, used to stomp the average citizen into abject
submission (such as the RIAA fraudulent lawsuits), the threat is real, serious,
and extensive.

Clearly Congress knows it too - if they didn't, they'd just toss out the
Constitution and the Copyright Act and save themselves and their paymasters a
lot of trouble.

Obviously, copyright and patent law should be thrown out - not only cannot
reasonable people agree on what they do or should mean, but even the Supreme
Court, Congress, and many attorneys who are VERY well versed in this contrivance
are unable to agree. Anytime you have such a poor "consensus" it's a
good sign something is broken - badly broken. In this case, it's "patently
clear" that the entire archaic concept of government-sanctioned monopolies
is an out-of-control monster.

NOBODY lives in a vacuum. The writer of Beauty and the Beast, or the Disney
animator, or the local playwright, ALL depended on knowledge and lore and effort
and results of 10,000 years or more of human endeavor. To try to lock that up
now is just plain WRONG. These are laws that should be circumvented, broken, or
just plain thrown overboard - I'm among those that believe that EVERY citizen of
the planet has a moral obligation to resist unjust laws. When the victims of
copyright abuses and the courts charged with "upholding the law"
cannot agree on even the most basic premises, it's time to say "Hey, you
know what? The framers WERE capable of mistakes, and THIS monstrosity is the
proof." Everybody thinks Jefferson, Washington, Franklin and the rest were
infallible. I'm absolutely certain they'd be the first to tell you: WRONG.

Now the only problem is: how do we buy back our Congress and get it out of
"Of, By, and For the Corporation"?

[ Reply to This | # ]

Key Escrow
Authored by: hbo on Sunday, September 09 2007 @ 05:50 PM EDT
The entertainment industry may want fair use not to be a right so they don't have to provide it and can DRM it into nothingness, mainly I would guess because no one can figure out yet how to DRM something *and* provide fair use.
I can't be the first person to think of this, but reading the above did make me realize there's a well established way to provide both DRM and fair use access, at least technically. Political, business and sociological considerations might make the idea impractical, but we can "figure out" how to provide both in technical terms. In Cryptology, there's a system known as "key escrow" which utilizes a trusted third party to mediate access to an encrypted text.

Here's a story about how it would work. Alice has a copyrighted work she wishes to publish using a DRM system The system uses public key cryptography to lock up the copyrighted text. This involves using two keys, each of which can decrypt text encrypted by the other. One of the keys is published, and the other is held private. Now, if one encrypts (writes) with the public key, only the private key can decrypt (read) the protected text. In the simplest key escrow scheme, the "private key" in addition to being distributed with approved readers, is stored with a trusted third party - let's call her Carol. Carol maintains public keys on behalf of copyright holders.

When another person, let's call him Bob, wants to access the encrypted text, he applies to Carol for permission. Carol may or may not be involved in "ordinary" access to the protected text. That is, she could be the one that licensed users apply to in order to "consume" the protected work. In that case, Carol would ask Alice if the particular use by the particular individual would be OK. (There are ways to implement this so neither Carol nor Alice know who Bob is, by the way. This alleviates concerns some may have about dossier building based on reading habits or other choices.)

The fair use case would work differently. If Bob apples to Carol for fair use access to the protected text, a different cryptographic protocol would be used that would result in a "non-repudiatable" transaction. That means Bob would reveal his identity to Carol, and the protocol would guarantee that Bob was the one who asked for the particular fair use case. Bob might or might not be required to give his rationale for the fair use. But crucially, Alice would not have a say in whether or not fair use access would be granted. All such requests would be granted by Carol as a matter of course. However, infringements on Alice's copyright by Bob would be instantly attributable to him, and to the request he made to Carol. So Alice could sue Bob for infringement. The flip side is that Bob could offer the affirmative defense of fair use, with an equally strong audit trail.

The scheme given here is probably full of weaknesses that could be exploited to overcome the system. In the first place, I'm not a mathematician, and it takes a math expert who has also made a rigorous study of Cryptology to design secure protocols. Also, a "secure" protocol in theory needs to be implemented in the real world, which often resits perfection in millions of unpredictable ways. In other words, "there's many a slip twixt cup and lip" applies. Nonetheless, the same considerations apply to DRM itself, so the two systems could be at least on an equal footing in that regard. I also believe that the simple outline I have given could be corrected and improved by experts.

What remains is political will and economic incentive to adopt this scheme. I'm pessimistic that either could be forthcoming in the present climate of hostility to individual rights. The worm may be turning on that one, though, so who knows?

Regards,
Howard

---
"Even if you are on the right track, you'll get run over if you just sit there" - Will Rogers

[ Reply to This | # ]

Some Questions
Authored by: sproggit on Sunday, September 09 2007 @ 06:04 PM EDT
PJ, as always, raises some excellent thoughts and discussion points here. Since she's got me thinking, I wanted to share my questions to see if sharper minds than mine could add to the ideas...


1. "Copy Protection" of digital Media [i.e. CDs and DVDs] Acknowledging that this is thin ice and a temporary solution at best... the first question relates to the changes that media companies would make when issuing CD/DVD/similar media that includes copy protection technologies. What happens if such mechanisms are extras, added as an after-thought to the original format?

Specifically, can a music company claim to sell me a "Music CD" if it also includes a root kit and/or other monitoring software? Does it still conform to the appropriate standard? If not, does that constitute false advertising?


2. Un-announced Copy Protection By default, un-protected audio CDs will play on my ubuntu Linux machine. Copy-protected audio CDs will not. Though at best my remedy in such situations is to return the product to the point of sale for a refund [typically at my expense if ordered via a web store], is there anything in appropriate legislation [in the UK it might be the "Sale of Goods Act" that sets down merchantability or suitability for purpose.


3. "No other warranties, expressed or implied" If I purchase a car with defective brakes that subsequently fail and as a result a pedestrian is killed, the government or relatives of a victim could sue the vehicle manufacturer on the basis that they have released a defective product. If I purchase an Operating System or other piece of software that I use to write a program that controls machinery and that machinery then malfunctions through a software bug, resulting in the accidental death of a machine operator, where does the software company stand with respect to their liability? If empirical evidence can recreate the malfunction with perfect consistency, does the "no warranties expressed or implied" clause in the license absolve software companies of all responsibilities? If so, who gave them the ability to claim such rights?


4. Ownership or Licensed Use? One of the latest and greatest tricks of computer software providers and music/video companies has been to change the wording of the EULA materials contained with their shipping products to the effect that customers are no longer purchasing a *copy* of the product, they are purchasing a *right to use* that could in theory be revoked at some future time. OK, fine. If all I am purchasing is a "right to use", what happens when I no longer "want to use" i.e. want to exercise that right? Since these companies should not be able to have things both ways, should I not therefore have the right to go back to the company and ask for a complete refund if I am willing to surrender the original media? [You can see where I'm going with that question...] Why should such a unilateral and clearly one-sided amendment to terms be permitted?


5. Rights to Privacy / Theft Back before specific laws were enacted that made "cracking", [note, explicitly not 'hacking'] a criminal offense, one of the most common ways for authorities to prosecute offenders was to charge them with "Theft of Electricity" - i.e. by connecting to servers without authorisation a hacker caused a computer to expend electrical energy responding to commands, thereby committing a theft. Fine. So what happens when an embedded agent or copy protection technology in a game tries to connect to the internet and report activity, or installs a hidden daemon process in a machine's registry that runs whenever the computer is active. What's the difference between a criminal gang writing a Trojan that turns a computer into a zombie and a software company writing a Trojan that turns the computer into an unwitting "informant"?


6. Data Protection Laws In most countries Data Protection Laws are carefully worded with respect to the ability of captured data to "identify an individual". In the UK, for example, citizens have the right to go to any company and demand to have a copy of all data that is being held about them. Companies are legally obliged to respond and may charge a maximum of £10 for the cost of providing their response. However, all such companies have to register their data storage with the UK government, i.e. the Data Protection Registrar.

So, if I purchase a copy of [for example] "BioShock" and software agents within the game start to link back to a 2KGames server and report information, including my IP Address and details of my computer, have 2KGames registered this feature with the UK Data Protection Registrar? What if that destination server is based in the US or another country with which the UK has not reached legal agreement on data protection measures?

What if, as in the case of Sony, the measures deployed render machines vulnerable to malicious attack? Where does liability rest?


7. Presumption of Innocence With respect to these "software agents"... it seems as though media companies are deploying them embedded within computer games because they fear that games themselves are subject to illicit copying. This, to me, is tantamount to a declaration that anyone who purchases a given game does so with the intention to make illicit copies. So the vendor is judging all purchasers [in absentia], finding them guilty, then taking measures into their own hands. OK, it probably isn't quite the same as "presumed innocence" but perhaps you see my point. Anyone got any thoughts onto whether or not it's permissible for the individual rights of a consumer to be curtailed in this way?


And as a thank-you for those who've had the patience to read this far, here's a link to a *very* thought-provoking article on a similar subject:-

Please Read Me


[ Reply to This | # ]

Fair Use: Affirmative Defense or Right? Do I Have to Choose?
Authored by: Anonymous on Sunday, September 09 2007 @ 06:43 PM EDT
Here's a question then. I have an open source project. If someone chooses to use
some aspect of it in another project under a different license scheme, but only
a portion, is that also fair use?

If it is, for example, used in a tutorial that is not under the gpl, are they
legally allowed to use it without placing their entire tutorial under the gpl?

Ok, in reality I'd be happy for the latter case to occur, that's pretty much
what my project is about. I can't see what use my work would have in the
proprietary world any way.

Does the pendulum swing both ways though? Can we claim fair use of copyrighted
work and then forbid use of portions of our own work unless it is under our own
license terms?

[ Reply to This | # ]

DRM vs Fair use
Authored by: PJP on Sunday, September 09 2007 @ 07:15 PM EDT
PJ says:

"The entertainment industry may want fair use not to be a right so they
don't have to provide it and can DRM it into nothingness, mainly I would guess
because no one can figure out yet how to DRM something *and* provide fair
use."

Unfortunately, I can think of ways that they could probably do this. For
example, along with your DRM-ed copy of the latest blockbuster, they deliver a
copy without DRM, but of such appaling quality that no-one would want to watch
it for entertainment. Similarly for audio products, an "open" version
with an audio range restricted to something like 500hz to 2.5khz - which would
sound like the same thing played over a poor telephone connection.

By doing this, they could claim that for the purposes of fair use, which are not
entertainment, the crappy copies are more than good enough.

[ Reply to This | # ]

Is a URL copyrightable?
Authored by: Anonymous on Sunday, September 09 2007 @ 07:22 PM EDT
After all I went through trying to figure out if I was allowed to link to some Pavarotti videos the other day, I decided I'd better study a bit more about fair use.
Wouldn't the matter of fair use relate to the link itself and not the material to which it points? The information that you include in your web page is a web link. The issue appears to actually be that of deep linking which doesn't appear well established under law. The copyright you would be violating would appear to be for the website where the pointer was found.

Should we ask if this pointer reference can be subject to copyright itself? The URL found in a link points to a location of a copyrighted work. If the originating page was from was a collection of links with basic information we'd expect it were the equivalent of a phone book, a compilation of facts. If the link were found as an incidental contained within a copyright protected work is it any more subject to copyright? Is the objecting author trying to protect the process of locating a work? Would you be safe providing a narrative on 'go to the website, click the link in the left column labeled ..'?

This presupposes that the target link is an authorized public display of a protected work. If that authorization is inherent in the URL without further mechanism for limiting access such as the equivalent of robots.txt or subscription, etc., are you violating that authorization by using the URL without first accessing some other location? I'd think that it is an authorized public display.

An alternate view might be that the entire authors work and any linked work be viewed as a composite work. A link makes a very small part of a composite work. If you can't link, how can you cite?

IANAL, etc.

[ Reply to This | # ]

DRM and DMCA are illegal!
Authored by: Anonymous on Sunday, September 09 2007 @ 09:55 PM EDT
Where the laws of the United States reflect it or not, the title line is a
statement of fact for two reasons.

1). Fair use, which PJ describes here.

2) But the later and more significant issue is to "KEEP" a copyright
work out of
public domain forever!

This latter reason is why DMCA was passed, it is an attempt by RIAA and
MPAA to keep works out the public domain for ever!

I'm an old grey bread, who has copyrighted works on 45's and LP's that have
not been released under any other media. When the copyright expires these
works will be lost to the public (public domain). With out fair use, the public

has no safe-guards against the work not being available to the public.

The goal of the RIAA and MPAA is to remove the public domain in forever!

Only diligent souls can safe-guard against this.

Be very afraid!

[ Reply to This | # ]

I don't know about fair use but...
Authored by: tellner on Monday, September 10 2007 @ 01:38 AM EDT
Consider self defense. It is certainly a right. Justice Felix Frankfurter called
it the most basic right. It is also an affirmative defense in use of force
cases. In fact, if the legal prerequisites are meant it is a perfect affirmative
defense.

So yes, something can be both. I have no idea whether fair use is analogous.

[ Reply to This | # ]

DRM does not preclude fair use
Authored by: Anonymous on Monday, September 10 2007 @ 03:02 AM EDT
DRM does not preclude fair use.

For example, if DRM makes it impossible to make an exact copy of a part of a
DVD, it is still possible to use a video camera to tape a copy of the work from

a computer screen or television screen or a film screen. It is easy to do. So

easy, pirates will take a camcorder into a theater to make copies.

As another example, DRM may make it difficult to make an exact copy of
music. But one can easily also just record the song - either on the computer
or using a tape recorder and microphone.

I think the issue of DRM is overblown since there are other ways to copy a
work. Yes, it won't be an EXACT copy. But a first or second generation copy
is still perfectly usable. If people are satisfied with 128 kbps songs that are

sold online with DRM, then a recording of a DRM'd song is perfectly fine.

If you can see it or hear it, then it can be recorded, even it it is DRM'd.

[ Reply to This | # ]

Fair Use: Affirmative Defense or Right? Do I Have to Choose?
Authored by: Anonymous on Monday, September 10 2007 @ 11:10 AM EDT
I think that from a practical point of view, industry wins
and individuals lose. This is because, although an individual may be right
under the constitution and laws,
that individual most likely cannot afford the financial
burden that must be assumed to be able to freely excercise
that right without persecution.

To state it another way, if I really do have the right to
do something, but Big Bully Inc. chooses to sue me
regardless, I lose because I cannot afford the legal costs. Therefore, out of
fear of being sued, I decide not to the
thing I wanted to do even if I really have the right to do it.


[ Reply to This | # ]

  • Yep.... - Authored by: Anonymous on Monday, September 10 2007 @ 07:43 PM EDT
    • Yep.... - Authored by: Anonymous on Wednesday, September 12 2007 @ 03:04 AM EDT
Fair Use: Affirmative Defense or Right? Do I Have to Choose?
Authored by: Anonymous on Monday, September 10 2007 @ 11:43 AM EDT
Copyright law is already for too long. Not only is it impossible to use the
works of anyone living, it is impossible for any one to use the works of anyone
they've ever known when alive. Even fifty years is too long. All context and
personal knowledge of the era is lost by the time the works enter the public
domain. There are no know referants for anyone living for any work currently in
the public domain. Do you have any personal knowledge, from having lived in the
era, of William Shakespear. Any study of the author's work is incomplete
without extensive research of associated works, and that is still second hand.
How many people are around to give you first hand insite into life during World
War Two, so you can completely underdstand what an author might really be saying
from a novel of that era.

Those who fail to learn from history are doomed to repeating it.

[ Reply to This | # ]

This case may be worth watching
Authored by: StudioBob on Monday, September 10 2007 @ 11:45 AM EDT

Although I hesitate to mention her, Paris Hilton is suing Hallmark Cards clicky here. Hallmark has been using celebrity's images and words for many years, in the context of satirical greeting cards. IIRC every US President since at least WWII has appeared on one or more of these cards, as have many film and television perfomers.

I thought satire was specifically protected fair use. Will this case try to chip away at that definition? Or is there really no case here?

---
Karma comes around
...Especially to liars and thieves.

[ Reply to This | # ]

Fantastic analysis, PJ. Thanks! [EOM]
Authored by: Anonymous on Monday, September 10 2007 @ 02:13 PM EDT
n/t

[ Reply to This | # ]

DO other "restrictions" nullify copyright?
Authored by: Anonymous on Monday, September 10 2007 @ 02:26 PM EDT
A number of years ago Jerry Pournelle wrote an article in BYTE magazine about
copyrights. He was writing as an author and software user. He suggested that
placing other restrictions on a "work" other than those restrictions
already codified in hte copyright laws would, in his opinion, nullify the
copyright holders rights under copyright.

For Example - A Book. You may buy a copy. you may let others read your copy. you
may give your copy away. you may sell your copy. You may not make copies and
disperse them in any way. You may destroy your copy. But if the author makes any
other restrictions then the copyright may no longer be valid.

So does DRM some how limit how you may handle your copy of some work? You may
not make copies - can someone read it off my web server? Does that mean I have
created more than one copy? Can I sell my copy to someone else and eliminate all
other copies in my possesion?

Borland used to have wording to the effect that you, as the owner of a
particular piece of software were allowed to use it on one computer at a time.
You could install it on whatever computers you owned, but you could only run it
on one computer at a time. Seems that they sold a whole batch of copies of Turbo
Pascal and Turbo C because they made it as easy to use as possible.

Was the idea of the Copyright to provide as open a system as possible, but with
a way of enforcing the rules only if the rules were violated? Kind of like
Innocent until proven guilty?

Does DRM now make the assumption that any use they don't pre-authorize is
illegal? But then I guess that is the idea of Fair Use?

[ Reply to This | # ]

More than just an Affirmative Defense
Authored by: Ruidh on Monday, September 10 2007 @ 03:16 PM EDT
Fair Use isn;t infringement which is forgivable. Under Title 17, Fair Use *isn't
infringement*. You can assert Fair Use as an affirmative defense, but you can
also seek a declaratory judgment of non-infringement on the strength of a Fair
Use argument. So, clearly, Fair Use is more than "just" an affirmative
defense, it is a limitation of the rights of the copyright holders which is
enforceable in court.

---
All my comments on this site are licensed under a Creative Commons License.
http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/2.0/

[ Reply to This | # ]

Fair Use: Affirmative Defense or Right? Do I Have to Choose?
Authored by: KAKMAN on Monday, September 10 2007 @ 03:55 PM EDT
If Fair Use interpretations and a built in DRM system prevents me from booting
up my computer to access my files, that's when I chuck away the hardware and go
back to pen, ink, paper (and recording tape, if that technology hasn't been
crippled or made obsolete). Using a computer (in the USA only I might add )will
become a tussle between technological oligarchs and their slaves and scofflaw
coding pirates, and, yes, won't that be fun? It sounds like bad cyberpunk
fiction to me.

[ Reply to This | # ]

Maybe copyright holders don't have rights either
Authored by: Anonymous on Monday, September 10 2007 @ 05:22 PM EDT
... since an affirmative defense to a charge of infringement could be "I
own the copyrights."

[ Reply to This | # ]

Fair Use: Affirmative Defense or Right? Do I Have to Choose?
Authored by: tanner andrews on Wednesday, September 12 2007 @ 12:48 PM EDT
So when the Copyright Alliance talks of fair use as being merely an affirmative defense, what is it saying

An affirmative defense is a thing that says, in effect, that even if all of the allegations of the complaint are true, the plaintiff shall have no relief.

Fair use is an affirmative defense. It admits the making of a copy or derivative work, without express permission. It goes on to say, in effect, that you do not need express permission because your use is permitted by law. The law gives you a right of fair use against the rights holder.

The rights holder need not plead that the use is not fair. Rather, because it is an affirmative defense, you as a fair user would be required to plead and prove that your use is fair. Infringement is presumed in the making of copies or derivative works, and you are obliged to overcome that presumption.

This regime has the unfortunate consequence that a large and well-heeled corporate rights holder can discourage criticism and other fair uses through litigation. Even if it is fair use to say ``such a book is badly written, see: here's a paragraph of the author's swill'', you can be sued. The publisher can make it very expensive for you even though you would ultimately be vindicated.

Courts appear to be remarkably stingy in awarding the statutory fees to successful copyright defendants. This is to the advantage of the large corporate rights holding plaintiff.

---
I am not your lawyer; please ignore above message.

[ Reply to This | # ]

Fair Use: Affirmative Defense or Right? Do I Have to Choose?
Authored by: Anonymous on Friday, September 14 2007 @ 04:09 AM EDT
The whole Hollywood media machine was built on copyright infringement. Fox
moved to California because it had lax copyright laws and he couldn't make his
clones in New York. Disney ripped off Buster Keaton for most of his early Mickey
Mouse stuff, and even now Disney Corp rips off *and re-copyrights* both
traditional and new tales and fables from various countries for their movies.
They don't even have the "fair use" defence: it was copying, pure and
simple.

They're all a lie built on theft and fraud, and are now pushing hard to stop
others from doing what they did.

[ Reply to This | # ]

Groklaw © Copyright 2003-2013 Pamela Jones.
All trademarks and copyrights on this page are owned by their respective owners.
Comments are owned by the individual posters.

PJ's articles are licensed under a Creative Commons License. ( Details )